2020年8月13日木曜日

ミラーニューロンと解離 19

In contrast, self-disturbance in schizophrenia has been studied and discussed throughout the history of modern psychiatry. Recently it is often discussed also in the context ofipseity disturbance”

Sass, LA (2013) self-disturbance and schizophrenia: structure, specificity, pathogenesis. Association Recherches en psychanalyse 16;119-132.

The self-disturbances in schizophrenia is far more distinct and severe. Take for example a schizophrenic person, Mr. A who observes a man walking on a street, noticing another pedestrian, a stranger  approaching him from a different direction.. Suddenly a voice in his head says “He is an enemy. He will attack you!” Mr. A immediately takes an offense for that person as the voice is his own thought. This type of hearing voice often referred to as “command hallucination” characterizes the nature of the self-disturbance of schizophrenics, where the individual experiences the voice of someone as though that someone is almost seamlessly merged with himself. This condition might instantly meet the criterial of the self-disturbance in four domains delineated by Jaspers.

Neurological basis of dissociative symptoms

The difficult problem that we are facing, as to whether we should understand personalities in DID as independent individual or “partial” or “incomplete” might be easier to handle if there is any neurological basis or “neural correlate” of these personalities. If a personality A happens to be “located” in the right hemisphere whereas the personality B resides in the left hemisphere, without any overlapping area or communication between them, we could assume that they are different and independent consciousnesses. However, no study has so far indicated that each personality has its distinct localization. The author would still make a case that so-called “split-brain experiment” (Gazzaniga,et al) , indicates something akin to the multiplicity of the personalities in different location in the brain, I will save this topic for any future opportunity for further elaboration.)

In the past I approached this issue with the concept of dynamic core model proposed by Edelman and Tononi.

In this article, I discuss what I call ‘‘the problem of otherness’’ in dissociative identity disorder, which addresses the extent to which we validate and recognize the perception of otherness in each part of personality (PP) regarding other PPs. The general trend is considered to not fully validate it, which seems to stem from the era of the Freud–Janet controversy, partly due to the conceptual ambiguity of the splitting of the mind in the sense of division vs. multiplication. Consequently, we tend to consider dissociation as a defensive and intentional act, at least when it was initiated, with an understanding that PPs are not structurally separated from each other, but are rather internally and dynamically connected to each other, and that a PP is somewhat causative to and responsible for another PP’s thoughts and behaviors. Here, I consider the hypothetical neuro-cognitive model that is based on the ‘‘dynamic core’’ model proposed by G. Edelman, where the neurological correlate of dissociative identity disorder is conceived as a simultaneous and multiple existence of a

‘‘dynamic core’’, which represents each PP as a unique and wholesome existence in the conscious.

Okano (2019) Problem of ‘‘otherness’’ in dissociative disorder European Journal of Trauma and Dissociation